In the previous
lesson we spoke of the significance of the terms ‘essence’,
‘energy’ and ‘person’ as perceived by the Cappadocian
Fathers and we afterwards spoke of the principles they
applied for the transferal of those terms into the realm of
Theology. These were the principles:
1st
With regard to the “that He is” of God, in other
words, the simple affirmation of His existence:
There
should be no doubt, no question that He exists, and that
this is imperative.
2nd
With
regard to the “what He is” of God:
This
corresponds to the essence of God, of which there is a
total ignorance and incapability for one speak of it.
Regardless of how close one may approach or reach God –
whether as an angel or as a saint – there will always be
something that shields the essence of God, as in the case of
Isaiah who saw God on His throne, but saw Him mantled by
angels. With their wings, they had somehow shrouded the
essence of God – the essence that cannot be seen by anyone,
or be perceived, or be known with the mind.
3rd
There can be no
bare essence.
Saint Basil the
Great had said this; in other words, there cannot be any
essence without a hypostasis – an essence that does not have
any hypostases within it. This means that when we speak of
the one God, or, when we speak of the one essence of God, we
must immediately also imply the persons – His three
Persons. The one does not precede the other, because quite
simply, the one cannot exist without any hypostasis, and the hypostatic form of God’s essence is triadic. That is
why we do not have essence without hypostasis. At this
point, we need to add the opposite observation – that there
cannot be a hypostasis without essence; in other words, it
is not correct for one to suppose that the hypostases are
precedent to the essence, as though they can be perceived on
their own, without essence. Essences without hypostases
do not exist, nor hypostases without essences. This is
the third principle, which places all three Persons at the
same level. The persons appear simultaneously (not meant in
the sense of time), as the hypostases of the essence.
Nevertheless, this togetherness, this simultaneousness of
the one and the many in God, bears the implication that
inside this simultaneousness, there is a certain gradation.
This gradation
is the other principle that the Cappadocians mainly
introduced. It is the gradation of causality; in
other words, this appearance of the three Persons is not
without a cause. Someone, something, causes this
hypostatizing of the essence. God is not hypostases; the
essence does not comprise hypostases without a cause. It is
precisely this cause which differentiates the Father (one of
the three Persons, of the three hypostases). It
differentiates Him, with regard to the other two hypostases.
The Cappadocian Fathers had to confront that precarious
tract from the Gospel of Saint John, which was used
exhaustively by the Arians against the orthodox. The
familiar statement “My Father is greater than me” was used
precisely in the context of the above meaning of causality.
The Father is
indeed greater than the Son, not in nature, not in essence,
but only from the aspect of causality, because the Father is
the cause. It is in this way that we have a prioritizing
of the hypostases, on the basis of causality. According
to the Cappadocian Fathers, it is this meaning of causality
that is absolutely related to the meaning of freedom.
When
we say that the cause is the Father, we firstly mean that
the birth of the Son and the sending forth of the Holy
Spirit were not an effluence of the essence (which would
imply that we have a precedence of the essence), nor were
they compulsory, in the sense that the persons – the
hypostases – are not antecedent to the essence, but in
another, more positive sense, i.e., that they reflect
freedom. And that is precisely the idea, the belief, i.e.,
that the hypostases – the persons – and consequently the
very existence of God, by having the Father as the cause,
and with the volition of the Father, they were “neither
unwanted nor unwilled by the Father”, as Saint Athanasius
had said.
In ‘wanting’
therefore (and for one to want, one must be a person), the
essence possesses the will, but the essence per se does not
possess the ‘wanter’. It possesses the ‘wanter’, only in
the person of a hypostasis, and not as the essence. The
meaning of causality is linked to the freedom of God’s being
to the extent that the ‘wanting’ Father is not only the
‘wanter’ of the Son’s and the Holy Spirit’s existence, but
He is also the ‘wanter’ of His own hypostasis, and His own
existence.
As Saint
Athanasius said: “the Father is the wanter of His very
hypostasis”; and this is because it would be inconceivable,
as Gregory the Theologian stressed, when responding to the
question “how is the Father hypostatized?” as it was
something that one would never even dare to consider.
Because when the Arians said “so, the Son is out of
necessity, and not willed”, Gregory had replied by saying
“consider the Father also: If you say that the Father exists
out of necessity, then it is as though you are saying the
most terrible, the most inconceivable thing, because “if the
Father exists without His wanting it, how can He be God, if
He is compelled? And this means nothing else, except one
thing – that He is God” (ει δε ου θέλων υφίσταται ο Πατήρ,
πώς Θεός,
ει βεβίασθαι.
και ταύτα ουκ άλλο τι ει αυτό το είναι Θεός).
In other words, you may say that God is not free - just like
you can say many other things – but to say that He is not
free to exist, is inconceivable. This means that the
freedom to be – the freedom to exist – is a basic thing for
God.
God’s existence
– His way of existence – is exactly His triadic hypostasis
of Father-Son-Holy Spirit, and this freedom as to their
existence applies to all three of His Persons, to the
Father, the Son and the Holy Spirit. What is the cause of
this freedom? It is not a freedom that originates from the
essence; it is the freedom of the causer – the Father. The
Father is the One who ‘wants’, and this can be seen in Saint
Athanasius’ words: “for the Son also, with the wanting that
the Father wants Him, by that same wanting He also loves and
honors and wants the Father; and one is the will of the
Father in the Son, so that thus, one can consider the Father
to be within the Son and the Son within the Father” (και γάρ ο Υιός τη θελήσει ή θέλεται,
παρά του Πατρός,
ταύτη και αυτός αγαπά και τιμά και θέλει τον Πατέρα∙
και έν εστί θέλημα το εκ Πατρός εν Υιώ ως και τούτον θεωρήσθαι τω Πατρί εν τω Υιώ και τω Υιώ εν τω Πατρί).
Consequently, with the Father being the cause, He is not
only the cause of the Son’s birth, and the coming forth of
the Holy Spirit – in other words the existence of the
Trinity or His own existence also – but He is also the cause
of voluntary (free) existence; that is, He exists
voluntarily and not compulsorily.
Consequently,
the issue is that the free will of the Father is whence
the triadic hypostasis of God springs from; from whence the essence is hypostatized into a triadic God. From
the moment that we say this (that the free will of the
Father hypostatizes itself, that it hypostatizes the essence
as Father, Son and Holy Spirit) we are risking the issue
that the Arians had identified and immediately
counter-proposed i.e., that if such is the case, the Son
must have therefore been born following a volition-will.
So, how can we reconcile the ‘refuting’ of Athanasius and
the Cappadocians that “the Son is born, not unwilled and
unwanted, but by the wanting of the Father Who wanted Him” (ουχί αβουλήτως και αθελήτως,
αλλά τη θελήσει του θέλοντος αυτώ Πατρός γεννάται ο Υιός)?
At first glance
we seem to have here a contradiction, which may create some
confusion…. We need to stress that there is no
contradiction, but we do need to first make a delicate
distinction, which arises from the study once again of the
writings of Athanasius and the Cappadocians. When
Athanasius opposed the Arian position that the Son is born
pursuant to the volition of the Father, he explains
the reason he has done this and he clearly defines the
meaning of volition that is implied in this instance:
He therefore
says: “as for saying that it (=the birth of the Son)
occurred after a volition, it first of all implies
that it might have never been, and furthermore, it also has
an inference of uncertainty, inasmuch as one could assume
that the Son could also not have been wanted.”
(το μεν γαρ λέγειν
εκ βουλήσεως γέγονε, πρώτον μεν το μη είναι ποτέ σημαίνει,
έπειτα δε και την επ άμφω ροπήν έχειν, ώστε δύνασθαι τινά
νοείν ότι ηδύνατο και μη βούλεσθαι τον Υιόν).
That which
bothered Athanasius, making him oppose the idea of Paternal
volition, was that the meaning of ‘volition’ there had the
inference which he had stressed elsewhere, as that which
“has a proclivity towards something other, and is
also indicative of something opposite, inasmuch as,
with the former, one must show preference, and with the
latter, one cannot show support” (επί θάτερα ροπήν έχοντος αυτού και δεικτικού του εναντίου,
ώστε τούτω μεν εκλέγεσθαι,
εκείνω δε μη ερείσθαι).
The meaning
of volition has precisely the meaning of choice.
If I am –for example- free to attend or not attend the
lesson (although that is not absolute), if I decide to do
it, then that’s fine. But, by deciding, and by being
free to choose to do it or not, I am implying that I could
just as equally choose to not do it. By being truly
free, I am able to choose to do or not do the lesson.
Therefore the term “of His volition” contains that inference
of “something other” – that “proclivity towards something other, which is also indicative of something
opposite,
so that with the former, one must show preference, and with
the latter, one cannot show support”. And that is exactly
what he means, if we apply the idea of “volition” to the
birth of the Son, i.e.: we would be implying that the Son
could equally not have been born.
But we must be
careful, that he does not mean it only in this way. That
which bothered him –and this is most revealing- is not so
much that the Son could equally not have been born, but that
“one could assume that the Son could also not have
been wanted”, in other words, that the Father could possibly
not have freely wanted the Son. The paradox here is the
following: Athanasius wants a volition that is free,
eternal and never-ending, but it must not be a
volition that requires a choice between two possibilities.
Athanasius is not opposed to free volition per se; he is
however against “volition” which implies a choice between
two possibilities, because that would imply that the Son
might not have been a volition of the Father;
according to Athanasius, the Son is eternally wanted by the
Father and he does not wish this to signify “necessity”. He
sees “volition” as “wanting”, thus making a proper usage of
words. Many of us would say that we can’t use the word
‘volition’, ‘wanting’ in that sense, and we thus deny free
will.
But then we
would be in a literal conflict with Athanasius. So, how can
we understand him in the essence? How can we reconcile
matters?
An eternal
wanting,
which does not contain the option of something opposite and
contrary? How can these two things be reconciled? We need
to delve very deeply into Patristic thinking here… Because
that is where the supreme mystery of freedom and existence
is hidden… in the way that the Fathers expounded it.
Let us examine
this very delicate point carefully: The fact that I could
attend or not attend this lesson – that I possess this
choice – is attributed to the fact that I am faced with
two given situations. They are given.
I do not create them; they are given. We make
choices, when we have before us two
possibilities. We do not create those possibilities; they
are given, and that is the characteristic definition of
the created. Because the created is precisely confronted by
a preexisting reality. Because it is created, i.e. it is
someone else’s creation, that ‘someone else’ – the creator –
obviously precedes the creation. The creation-created
therefore is presented with the challenge - if given
the freedom – to either accept or to not accept that
which is precedent to it, as Adam was. Adam found himself
in front of this choice-selection, i.e., whether to say
‘yes’ to God, or ‘no’. Because God had preceded Adam, and
whatever is precedent – whatever we find ready – is a
challenge to our freedom. For instance, you have this table
in front of you; you are free to either kick it, or to do
whatever you want with it. It is a challenge to my freedom,
to take a stance opposite that table. It is a
characteristic of the creation-created, to be faced with
already existing situations, amongst which it will make its
choices.
Let us try to
apply this meaning of freedom to God – the Uncreated – and
in fact apply it “before” the existence of the world. So,
how do we apply it to the eternal, never-ending existence of
God? What choices can someone make, when there is nothing
else around them except their self? The dilemma would then
be : either they will exist compulsorily and be subservient
to their self, their essence, their nature, or, they will
exercise freedom in only one way: affirmatively, positively,
with a ‘yes’. Because, who would they say ‘no’ to ? You
say ‘no’, when you reject something near you. But what can
you reject, when there is nothing around you to reject? Do
you reject yourself? This is a schizophrenic kind of
situation, which again originates from the option for choice
that we the created have. When we reject our self, it is
because our self is –to us- a given existence. We ourselves
did not decide to be born; our freedom was not operative
during our birth. The fact that we are (previously) created
is what gives us the option to commit suicide – to reject
our self. So, if we remove the element of creation, we
naturally cannot consider God committing suicide, or His
exercising freedom in a negative way, with a ‘no’ by Him.
Because ‘no’ signifies a rejection, and there would be
nothing for Him to reject.
So, God is left
with this: Either He is compulsorily existent, or, for Him
to be free, He must exercise His freedom by responding
affirmatively, by saying ‘yes’ to His existence, because the
option to say ‘no’ does not exist; because there is nothing
else beyond Him.
God, within His
own existence, is not alone. His very existence is an
ontological ‘yes’. Subsequently, His freedom coincides
with His very existence. The ‘yes’ of His existence is
the ‘yes’ of His freedom, and the ‘yes’ of His existence
contains the ‘yes’ of His triadic existence. When the Father
consents to His own existence and the existence of the Son
and the Holy Spirit, He is exercising freedom. And He is
exercising His freedom, as an affirmative will. This
affirmative will allows no margin for a negative will - as
that would be something inconceivable for the Uncreated –
and this is precisely what is known as
the love of God.
It is not by
chance that Saint Athanasius in this crucial excerpt relates
the will of God to the love of God. He says: “Just as He
–the Father- is the wanter of His own hypostasis, likewise
is the Son, being of the same essence, is not unwanted by
Him-the Father. Therefore the Son is wanted and loved by the
Father; and thus, one must respectfully consider that which
is wanted and not unwilled by God” (ώσπερ γαρ της ιδίας αυτού υποστάσεως εστί θελητής,
ούτω και ο Υιός,
ίδιος ων αυτού της ουσίας ουκ αθέλητος εστίν αυτώ.
Θελέσθω και φιλέσθω
τοίνυν ο Υιός παρά του Πατρός• και ούτω το θέλειν και το μη
αβούλητον του Θεού τις ευσεβώς λογιζέσθω)
». Thus, we see that there is a way that we can have an
orthodox approach to the “wanting and not unwilled” by God,
and there is a way that we can have a “wanting and not
wanting” by God.
It is a
perception of cacodoxy, when the will of God is perceived as
a decision of choosing between options. However, this is not
the only interpretation of ‘will’ that exists. There is
also the pious meaning of ‘will’, the orthodox concept of
‘will’. It is the “Son being wanted and loved by the
Father; and thus, one must respectfully consider that which
is wanted and not unwilled by God” (θελέσθω και φιλέσθω ο Υιός παρά του Πατρός και ούτω το θέλειν και το μη αβούλητον του Θεού ευσεβώς τις λογιζέσθω).
When,
therefore,
(as Saint Cyril of Alexandria explains Saint Athanasius) the
will of God goes along with His nature, then God’s freedom
coincides with His existence, and it is not an issue of the
freedom of ‘yes’ or ‘no’. It is the freedom of ‘yes’ only.
It should be noted that Maximus the Confessor proposed the
concept of freedom as a one-way street and not two streets,
which we must choose between. This is precisely the concept
of freedom that prevails in theosis. Eschatologically, we
will not have the option of choice. Even with death, choices
are not an option (there is no repenting in Hades), but with
the Second Coming, when I choose freely to say ‘no’ to
killing someone (and death has been abolished in the
meantime), then what is the significance of my freedom?
Eschatologically, my freedom becomes a one-way street. It
becomes the ‘yes’. That is why it is characteristic in
theosis. ‘Yes’ is God’s way of existence, as Paul says in
his Epistle II to Corinthians: “Christ is not a ‘yes’ and
‘no’ to us, but everything is become ‘yes’ in Him” (ουκ εγένετο ημάς ο Χριστός ναι και ου,
αλλά ναι εν αυτώ γέγονε).
The ‘yes’ does not imply compulsoriness and non-freedom.
God is the God of ‘yes’ in His existence. He is an eternal
‘yes’ towards the Son and the Spirit, which ‘yes’ is
reciprocated by the Son and the Spirit, towards the Father.
Consequently,
there is a respectful way of referring to the “wanting and
not unwilled by the eternal God”. This is the respectful
way.
The Father
therefore freely and out of love gives birth to the Son and
sends forth the Spirit.
Freely and out of love. Because this “wanting and loving by
the Son, and the Son’s being wanted and loved by the
Father” (θέλειν και φιλείν τον Υιόν,
θελέσθω και φιλέσθω ο Υιός παρά του Πατρός),
is precisely equivalent to the existence of the Son; to the
Son’s being. Thus, “by the wanting that the Son is wanted
by the Father, by the same wanting He likewise wants and
loves the Father; and the wanting is mutual.”
(τη θελήσει η θέλεται παρά
του Πατρός ο Υιός ταυτή και αυτός αγαπά και θέλει και τιμά
τον Πατέρα• και εν εστί θέλημα).
When a creation
makes a choice, we can have a variety of wills/wants. The
freedom of a creation allows for various wills/wants,
whereas here, freedom entails only one will. God’s will is
only one, and that is why it is linked to His one nature, to
His one essence: “and one is the will, of the Father in the
Son” (και εν εστί θέλημα,
το εκ Πατρός εν Υιώ).
It may be only one will, but it is not characteristic of
the essence. It could be characteristic of the essence,
but it does not originate from the essence. When we say “of
the Father”, we mean that the will originates from Him; that
He wills/wants to exist as God, and that is why the Father
–par excellence– is God. In the Bible, God=Father and
according to the Greek Fathers, God=Father. Only to the
Westerners is He is an essence…. From Augustine onwards…
Therefore the
Father –as the cause- is the One Who freely wills His very
hypostasis – the hypostasis of the Trinity,
and it is with
this, that we should confront the problem that arises with
the Arians, when Athanasius rejects “volition” without
rejecting “wanting and not unwilled”. The contradiction
therefore which –at first glance– this concept presents, is
lifted and is solved in this manner. The subject is very,
very difficult.